back to main page

James Green-Armytage

 

Voting methods: definitions and criteria

 

Contents:
PRELIMINARY DEFINITIONS
      
Pairwise comparison, pairwise defeat, pairwise tie
DEFINITIONS AND CRITERIA RELATING TO MAJORITY RULE
      
Majority criterion

       Mutual majority criterion
      
Condorcet winner, Condorcet criterion
      
Condorcet loser, Condorcet loser criterion
      
Majority rule cycle
      
Condorcet completion method
      
Minimal dominant set and Smith criterion
      
Summary of majority rule criteria

DEFINITIONS RELATING TO DEFEAT STRENGTH
      
Margins
      
Winning votes
      
Cardinal pairwise
      
Immune set 

DEFINITIONS RELATING TO STRATEGY
      
Compromising strategy
      
Burying strategy
      
Paradoxical strategy
      
Compression and reversal
      
Counterstrategy

       Strategy definition summary

CONTINUITY CRITERIA
       Monotonicity criterion
      
Participation criterion
      
Consistency

       Continuity criteria summary
MISCELLANEOUS CRITERIA

       Pareto
      
Later preferences criterion
      
Independence of clones

       Miscellaneous criteria summary

Criteria definitions for non-ranked methods

Acknowledgements and endnotes

 

PRELIMINARY DEFINITIONS

 

Preliminary note on > and = symbols: I use these in two slightly different ways. For example, “A>B” can mean that an individual voter or a specific set of voters ranks A above B, and it can also mean that A has a pairwise victory over B. “A=B” can signify an equal ranking of A and B, or a pairwise tie between A and B. The meaning will be made clear by the context.

 

Pairwise comparison, pairwise defeat, pairwise tie: A pairwise comparison uses ranked ballots to simulate head-to-head contests between different candidates.

            Given two candidates A and B, there is a pairwise defeat of B by A if and only if A is ranked above B on more ballots than B is ranked above A.

            If the number of A>B ballots is equal to the number of B>A ballots, then there is a pairwise tie between A and B. For the purpose of a pairwise tally, all candidates who are not ranked on a given ballot are considered to be tied for last place on that ballot.

 

Example 1, preferences:

49 voters: A>B>C

24 voters: B>A>C

24 voters: B>C>A

3 voters: C>B>A

 

            Imagine that 100 votes were cast as above, between candidates A, B, and C. We want to do pairwise comparisons between all candidates, so that means comparing A with B, A with C, and B with C. The table below illustrates how these pairwise comparisons are performed.

 

 

A>B

B>A

A>C

C>A

B>C

C>B

49: A>B>C

49

 

49

 

49

 

24: B>A>C

 

24

24

 

24

 

24: B>C>A

 

24

 

24

24

 

3: C>B>A

 

3

 

3

 

3

total

49

51

73

27

97

3

 

            You can see that 49 voters prefer A to B, whereas 51 voters prefer B to A. Hence, B wins its pairwise comparison with A, 52-48. Likewise, A beats C  (73-27), and B beats C (97-3). I often express this information as follows:

 

Example 1, pairwise comparisons:

B>A : 51-49

A>C : 73-27

B>C : 97-3

            The same data can also be expressed as a matrix:

 

A B C
A 49 73
B

51

97
C

27

3

 

 

            A's row represents A's score in pairwise comparisons with the candidates of each column. The same goes for the other rows. If A's score is greater than C's in the A-C comparison, A's score represents a pairwise victory, and C's score represents a pairwise defeat.. For visual learning purposes, I've put the winning scores above in blue, and the losing scores in red. If a candidate's row consists entirely of victories (as in the case of B above), that candidate is a Condorcet winner (defined below). If a candidate's row consists entirely of defeats (as in the case of C above), that candidate is a Condorcet loser (defined below).

            One can also visually represent the result of pairwise comparisons by drawing an arrow from the winner to the loser, and writing the winning and losing scores next to the arrow, as below:

                                                                        

 

 

DEFINITIONS AND CRITERIA RELATED TO

MAJORITY RULE

 

Majority criterion (MC): If more than half of the voters rank candidate X over every other candidate, then the winner should be candidate X.

Some methods that pass MC: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, minimax, plurality [*], IRV, two round runoff

Some methods that fail MC: approval [*], ratings summation, Borda

 

Mutual majority criterion (MMC): If there is a single majority of the voters who rank every candidate in a set over every candidate outside that set, then the winner should always be a member of the set.

 

Example 2, preferences:

45: A>B>C

30: B>C>A

25: C>B>A

 

            The smallest mutual majority set is {B, C}, because the 30 B>C>A voters and the 25 C>B>A voters rank the candidates in that set above candidate A. Methods that pass the mutual majority criterion will not elect candidate A in this example.

 

Some methods that pass MMC: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, IRV, Raynaud

Some methods that fail MMC: approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, minimax, plurality [*], two round runoff

 

Condorcet winner (CW), Condorcet criterion: A Condorcet winner, also called a ‘dominant candidate,’ is a candidate that wins all of its pairwise comparisons.

            If a voting method always elects a Condorcet winner when one exists, the method is Condorcet-efficient, and passes the Condorcet criterion.

 

Repeating example 1, pairwise comparisons:

B>A : 51-49

A>C : 73-27

B>C : 97-3

 

            Candidate B is the Condorcet winner, because it wins all of its pairwise comparisons.

 

Some methods that pass the Condorcet criterion: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, minimax

Some methods that fail the Condorcet criterion: approval [*], ratings summation, plurality [*], IRV, Borda, two round runoff

 

Condorcet loser, Condorcet loser criterion: A candidate that loses all of its pairwise comparisons is known as a Condorcet loser.

            A method that never selects a Condorcet loser passes the Condorcet loser criterion.

 

Repeating example 1, pairwise comparisons:

B>A : 51-49

A>C : 73-27

B>C : 97-3

 

            Candidate C is the Condorcet loser, because it loses all of its pairwise comparisons.

 

Some methods that pass the Condorcet loser criterion: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, IRV, Borda, two round runoff

Some methods that fail the Condorcet loser criterion: minimax, approval [*], ratings summation, plurality [*]

 

Majority rule cycle: A circular series of pairwise defeats (e.g. A beats B, B beats C, C beats A) that leaves no single candidate unbeaten.

 

Example 2, preferences:

35: A>B>C

33: B>C>A

32: C>A>B

 

Example 2, pairwise comparisons:

A>B : 67-33

B>C : 68-32

C>A : 65-35

 

            You can see that each candidate is defeated in one pairwise comparison. A is defeated by C, C is defeated by B, and B is defeated by A. There is no Condorcet winner (or Condorcet loser) in this example.

 

Condorcet completion method: A method that chooses the Condorcet winner when one exists, and that also includes a rule for choosing a winner when no Condorcet winner exists. Dozens of Condorcet completion methods have been proposed, including minimax, Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, Schwartz sequential dropping, beatpath, ranked pairs, river, cardinal pairwise, approval-weighted pairwise, Black, Nanson, Copeland, and so on.

 

Minimal dominant set: Also known as the Smith set and the GeTChA set. The smallest set of candidates such that every candidate within the set has a pairwise victory over every candidate outside the set.

Smith criterion: A method that always chooses from the minimal dominant set is Smith-efficient, and passes the Smith criterion.[*]

 

Some methods that pass the Smith criterion: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise

Some methods that fail the Smith criterion: IRV, minimax, approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, plurality [*], two round runoff

 

Summary of majority rule criteria:

            The table below summarizes the compliance/noncompliance of 6 methods with the 5 majority rule criteria (the majority criterion, mutual majority criterion, Condorcet criterion, Condorcet loser criterion, and Smith criterion). 

 

 

plurality

approval

Borda

IRV

minimax

ranked pairs

MC

pass

fail

fail

pass

pass

pass

MMC

fail

fail

fail

pass

fail

pass

Condorcet

fail

fail

fail

fail

pass

pass

Condorcet loser

fail

fail

pass

pass

fail

pass

Smith

fail

fail

fail

fail

fail

pass

            The non-compliances of approval voting as shown above (and elsewhere on the page) are shared by the ratings summation method. The compliances of ranked pairs as shown above are shared by several Condorcet completion methods, including beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, sequential dropping, and so on.

 

 

DEFINITIONS RELATING TO

DEFEAT STRENGTH

 

            When there is a majority rule cycle, many pairwise methods choose the winner by assigning a strength value to the different pairwise defeats, in order to decide which defeat(s) to overturn.

            Here are a few definitions of defeat strength. Note that margins and winning votes use only ordinal (ranking) information, but cardinal pairwise uses cardinal (rating) information as well.

 

Margins: Defines the strength of an A>B pairwise defeat as the number of A>B voters minus the number of B>A voters.

 

Winning votes (WV): Defines the strength of an A>B pairwise defeat as the number of A>B voters.

            Margins-based and winning votes-based methods produce the same result unless some voters give equal rankings to some candidates (or truncate their ballots).

 

Example 2.1, preferences:

45: A>B=C

12: B>A=C

14: B>C>A

29: C>B>A

 

Pairwise comparisons:

A>C : 45-43 (45 winning votes, with a margin of 2 votes) 

C>B : 29-26 (29 winning votes, with a margin of 3 votes)

B>A : 55-45 (55 winning votes, with a margin of 10 votes)

 

            In margins-based methods, the weakest defeat is A>C, with a margin of 2 votes. In winning votes-based methods, the weakest defeat is C>B, with 29 winning votes. Thus, C wins most margins-based methods, whereas B wins most winning votes-based methods. 

 

Cardinal pairwise: Defines the strength of an A>B pairwise defeat as follows: For each A>B voter, and only for A>B voters, subtract B’s rating from A’s rating, to get the rating differential. Sum the A>B rating differentials to get the A>B defeat strength.[*]

 

Immune set: The set of candidates such that any defeat against a candidate within the set is countered by a string of stronger (or equally strong) defeats leading back to the defeating candidate. There is an immune set definition for each possible defeat strength definition, e.g. the WV-defined immune set, the margins-defined immune set, the CWP-defined immune set.[*]

 

Repeating example 2, pairwise comparisons:

A>B : 67-33

B>C : 68-32

C>A : 65-35

 

            {A} is both the WV-defined immune set and the margins-defined immune set for this example. It’s true that C beats A, but A beats B, B beats C, and the A>B and B>C defeats are both stronger than the C>A defeat.

            The cardinal pairwise immune set cannot be defined for this example because no rating information is available.

 

 

DEFINITIONS RELATED TO

STRATEGY

 

Compromising strategy: Insincerely ranking (or rating) an option higher in order to decrease the probability that a less-preferred option will win. For example, if my sincere preferences are R>S>T, a compromising strategy would be to vote S>R>T or R=S>T, raising S’s ranking in order to decrease T’s chances of winning. (The drawback is that this often decreases R’s chances of winning as well.)[*]

 

            Condorcet-efficient methods minimize the incentive for the compromising strategy. All resolvable voting methods that satisfy the mutual majority criterion have a compromising incentive when there is a majority rule cycle. But voters in Condorcet-efficient methods never have an incentive to use the compromising strategy when there is a Condorcet winner. This is an important property because, in the absence of a majority rule cycle, it allows me to vote my R>S preference without worrying that it will undermine my S>T preference. This is a more complete way of curtailing the “lesser of two evils” problem, that is, decreasing the extent to which voters have to worry about earlier choices drawing support away from later choices.

 

Example 3, sincere preferences:

36: Right>Center>Left

15: Center>Right>Left

15: Center>Left>Right

34: Left>Center>Right

 

            In IRV, Center is eliminated first, and Right is the winner. However, if at least 5 of the Left voters vote Left=Center>Right or Center>Left>Right, then Left will be eliminated first, and their second choice, Center, will win instead of their third choice, Right. This would constitute a successful compromising strategy.

 

Burying strategy: Insincerely ranking (or rating) an option lower in order to increase the probability that a more-preferred option will win. For example, if my sincere preferences are R>S>T, a burying strategy would be to vote R>T>S or R>S=T, lowering S’s ranking in order to increase R’s chances of winning. (The drawback is that this often increases T’s chances of winning as well.)[*]

            Burying strategies can only be successful in methods that fail the later preferences criterion (defined below).

 

Example 4a, sincere preferences:

46: A>B>C

44: B>A>C

5: C>A>B

5: C>B>A

 

Example 4b, pairwise comparisons:

A>B 51-49

A>C 90-10

B>C 90-10

 

            Candidate A is the sincere Condorcet winner, and thus wins with any Condorcet completion method if votes are sincere. However, in many Condorcet completion methods, it is possible for the B supporters to change the result to their advantage.

 

Example 4b, includes some insincere preferences:

46: A>B>C

44: B>C>A (sincerely B>A>C)

5: C>A>B

5: C>B>A

 

Example 4b, pairwise comparisons:

A>B 51-49

C>A 54-46

B>C 90-10

 

            Now there is a majority rule cycle. Margins and WV define the A>B defeat to be the weakest in the cycle, and hence many margins and WV methods elect B as a result of the altered preferences. This constitutes a successful burying strategy.

 

Paradoxical strategy: Insincerely ranking an option lower in order to increase the probability that the same option will win, or insincerely ranking an option higher in order to decrease the probability that the same option will win.

            Paradoxical strategies can only be successful in methods that fail the monotonicity criterion.

 

Example 5a, sincere preferences:

38: A>B>C

10: A>C>B

9: B>A>C

18: B>C>A

25: C>B>A

 

            Given sincere votes, B is the winner in IRV. However, supporters of candidate A can use a paradoxical strategy to their advantage.

 

Example 5b, some insincere preferences:

38: A>B>C

5: A>C>B

5: C>A>B (sincerely A>C>B)

9: B>A>C

18: B>C>A

25: C>B>A

 

            Now, B is eliminated first instead of C, and the 9 B>A>C votes transfer to A, allowing it to defeat B 52-48 in the runoff.

            Note that paradoxical strategies in IRV tend to be more difficult to use than burying strategies in most Condorcet  completion methods, in that coordination and information usually need to be extremely precise in the former, and the risk/reward ratios tend to be higher.

 

Compression strategy: Any strategy that involves insincerely ranking two candidates equally (includes strategic truncation).

Reversal strategy: Any strategy that involves insincerely reversing the relative order in which two candidates are ranked.

Compromising-compression: A compromising strategy that involves insincerely giving two candidates an equal ranking.

Compromising-reversal: A compromising strategy that involves insincerely reversing the order of two candidates on the ballot.

Burying-compression: A burying strategy that involves insincerely giving two candidates an equal ranking.

Burying-reversal: A burying strategy that involves insincerely reversing the order of two candidates on the ballot. 

  

            For example, if my sincere preferences are R>S>T...

1. If I vote R=S>T in order to decrease T’s chances of winning, this is a compromising-compression strategy. 

2. If I vote S>R>T in order to decrease T's chances of winning, this is a compromising-reversal strategy. 

3. If I vote R>S=T in order to increase R's chances of winning, this is a burying-compression strategy.

4. If I vote R>T>S in order to increase R's chances of winning, this is a burying-reversal strategy.

 

Counterstrategy: A strategy by one group of voters that is intended to render ineffective a strategy by another group of voters.

Compromising counterstrategy: Insincerely ranking (or rating) an option higher in order to protect it from a burying strategy.

Burying/deterrent counterstrategy: Insincerely ranking (or rating) an option lower in order to make that option less likely to win as a result of a burying strategy.

            For an example of these two counterstrategies, see part 7.d. (stable counterstrategies) of my cardinal pairwise paper.

 

 

CONTINUITY CRITERIA

Monotonicity criterion: Raising the position of X on one or more ballots should never change the winner from X to any other candidate.

 

Some methods that pass monotonicity: minimax, Smith/minimax, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise (without maximizing in scale provision), approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, plurality [*]

Some methods that fail monotonicity: IRV, Raynaud, sequential dropping, two round runoff

 

Participation criterion: Adding ballots that rank X over Y should never change the winner from X to Y.

 

Some methods that pass participation: approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, plurality [*]

Some methods that fail participation: IRV, two round runoff, all Condorcet-efficient methods 

 

Consistency: If X is the winner given one set of ballots, and X is also the winner given another set of ballots, then if the two sets of ballots are pooled together, the winner should still be X.

Some methods that pass consistency: approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, plurality [*]

Some methods that fail consistency: IRV, two round runoff, all Condorcet-efficient methods

 

Summary of continuity criteria:

            The table below summarizes the compliance/noncompliance of 6 methods with 3 continuity criteria.

 

 

plurality

approval

Borda

IRV

minimax

ranked pairs

monotonicity

pass pass pass fail pass pass

participation

pass pass pass fail fail fail

consistency

pass pass pass fail

fail

fail

 

 

MISCELLANEOUS CRITERIA

 

Pareto: If all voters rank X over Y, then Y should not win.

Some methods that pass Pareto: minimax, Smith/minimax, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, approval [*], ratings summation, Borda, plurality [*], IRV, Raynaud, sequential dropping

Some methods that fail Pareto: approval

 

Later preferences criterion: Changing the order of preferences listed after a given candidate on one or more ballots shouldn’t increase or decrease the probability of that candidate being elected.

 

Some methods that pass the later preferences criterion: IRV, two round runoff, plurality [*]

Some methods that fail the later preferences criterion: all Condorcet-efficient methods, Borda, ratings summation, approval [*]

 

Clones: A set of candidates such that no ballots rank a non-member of the set in between two members of the set or equal to any member of the set.

Independence of clones: If a clone set has two or more members, removing one of the clones should not have any bearing on whether the winning candidate comes from the set. Likewise, adding a new clone to the set should not have any bearing on whether the winning candidate comes from the set.[*]

 

Some methods that are independent of clones: ranked pairs, beatpath, river, IRV, Raynaud

Some methods that are not independent of clones: minimax, Smith/minimax, approval [*], sequential dropping, cardinal pairwise, Borda, plurality [*], ratings summation, two round runoff

Notes: Borda's independence of clones failure is arguably much more severe than that of any other method above. Approval, ratings summation and cardinal pairwise pass a modified version of the criteria that requires each voter to give the same rating to all member of a set for it to qualify as a clone set.

 

Summary of miscellaneous criteria:

            The table below summarizes the compliance/noncompliance of 6 methods with 3 miscellaneous criteria.

 

 

plurality

approval

Borda

IRV

minimax

ranked pairs

Pareto

pass fail pass pass pass pass

later preferences

pass fail fail pass fail fail

indep. of clones

fail fail fail pass fail pass

 

_____________________________

 

Note on criteria definitions for non-ranked methods

       In the interest of simplicity, most definitions on this page, as written above, assume ranked ballots. However, some methods evaluated on this page (i.e. plurality and approval) do not use ranked ballots, and do not allow complete orderings when there are more than two candidates. I apply ranked ballot criteria to non-ranked methods as follows.  

 

1. Change ranking-based wording to preference-based wording. For example, a criterion with the wording "a voter ranks A over B" is changed to "a voter prefers A to B". The wording "a voter ranks A equal to B" is changed to "a voter is indifferent between A and B". 

2. Assume that votes are cast sincerely. In order to do this, I provide an operational definition of sincerity for plurality ballots and for approval ballots.

2a. Assume that a sincere vote on a plurality ballot entails voting for one's favorite candidate.

2b. Assume that an insincere vote on an approval ballot entails approving B but not approving A, if the voter prefers A to B, or is indifferent between A and B. 

Note: I am not entirely convinced by either of these definitions (in 2a or 2b), but they seem to serve our current purpose as well as anything else. Other applications are possible, and strictly speaking it's hard to argue that any single application is definitively correct. One approach is to ignore the possibility of unexpressed preferences and evaluate plurality and approval only with respect to expressed preferences. In that case, they pass just about anything you can think of, but this doesn't tell us very much, or capture the intent of the criteria themselves. Hence, I use the methods above for my tables. 

Note also that alternate (more restrictive) definitions for sincere approval voting, such as voting for candidates that provide utility above a certain threshold, or voting for the candidates in the top half of one's ranking, produce the same results for the criteria listed on this page.  

 

       For example, the majority criterion for ranked methods is : "If more than half of the voters rank candidate X over every other candidate, then the winner should be candidate X."

       To apply the majority criterion to non-ranked methods, it can be re-worded as follows: "If more than half of the voters prefer candidate X over every other candidate, and votes are sincere, then the winner should be candidate X."

       For cardinal ratings methods with more possible ratings than candidates, ranked ballot criteria can usually be applied without the need to use preference-based rather than vote-based definitions. For example, the majority criterion can be worded as follows: "If more than half of the voters give candidate X a higher rating than any other candidate, the winner should be candidate X."  

_____________________________

 

Acknowledgements

 

       Very few of the definitions and criteria listed and explained in this document originated with me. This page is not intended not as a statement of entirely new information but rather a new compilation and synthesis of work that is already available elsewhere. Hence, in the creation of this page I am entirely indebted to the larger voting methods community.  

       In wording the criteria, and in stating which methods pass and fail which criteria, I made use of several internet-based sources, including the following: 

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/

http://condorcet.org/emr/criteria.shtml

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Category:Voting_system_criteria

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Category:Voting_system_criteria

       However, I am responsible for any errors that I have made. This page is entirely new as of April 2005, so it is likely that errors will exist at this point. If you find a mistake, I encourage you to e-mail me. My current e-mail address is armytage at econ.ucsb.edu I also encourage you to e-mail me if you have any comments or questions about the site.

 

Endnotes

 

* Minimal dominant set/Smith set. See: 

Smith, J.H. (1973) "Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate," Econometrica, vol. 41, pages 1027-1041.

and

Schwartz, T. (1986) The logic of collective choice. New York: Columbia University Press. Page 141.

 

* Cardinal pairwise. See:

Green-Armytage, J. (2004) "Cardinal-weighted pairwise comparison," Voting Matters, issue 19, pages 6-13.

http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE19/ISSUE19.PDF

 

* Immune set. First defined by Jobst Heitzig, here:

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-May/012801.html

 

* The "compromising" and "burying" strategies were initially defined by Blake Cretney. My definitions are only slightly adapted from his. See:

http://condorcet.org/emr/defn.shtml

 

* Independence of clones. See:

Tideman, T.N. (1987) Independence of clones as a criterion for voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare 4: 185-206.

 

 

 

 

© James Green-Armytage. First created in April of 2005. Please cite the author when reproducing any portion of this document.